Skip to main content

D. M. ARMSTRONG’S DOCTRINE OF BEING

In Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics, D. M. Armstrong sets out to give a basic, and simplified, outline of his metaphysical positions.[1] Armstrong does not make any explicit attempt to deal with the problem of Being qua Being. However, an attentive lecture of his book will reveal what could be qualified as a modified, and over-simplified, Aristotelian response to the problem of Being. The following survey and attempted systematization of Armstrong's doctrine of Being deals exclusively with the book mentioned in the first sentence.

 Armstrong is more worried about beings than Being, however, he does explain that Being simply is synonymous with Existence and Actuality. “The Actual may be identified as existence, as being.”[2] To be is, therefore, to exist or to be actual. In conjunction with this claim Armstrong also asserts that there are no gradations of being.[3] Either a thing is or it is not, it exists or it does not exist, it has being or it does not have being. Armstrong does not develop the question of being much further than this; rather he spends most of his time discussing the types of things that have being, or which do not have being.

The first important point that we must understand about Armstrong’s doctrine of being, if we can say that he has one, is that he assumes, as a starting point, that the sum total of all that has being includes no non-natural entities. In his own words, the first sentence of his book, “I begin with the assumption that all that exists is the space-time world, the physical world as we say.”[4] As such, the first thing that we need to know about Armstrong’s doctrine of being is that the only things that have being are entities that are limited by space and time, and empirically observable. Any being which by definition does not fit within these limitations is nothing more than a concept and has no being.[5]

With this important distinction in mind we can move on to the next distinction. Armstrong accepts the distinction between Necessity and Contingency. He argues that necessary being are impossible; that is, there is no being that corresponds to the description Necessary.[6] As such, the only beings that could possibly exist are those that fit under the concept of contingency. However, Armstrong distinguishes between possible contingent beings and actual contingent beings. He claims that only those contingent beings which are actual, actually have being. In his own words, “to be possible and no more is not to have being.”[7] Therefore, possible contingent beings do not have being, actual contingent beings have being.

With these distinctions in mind Armstrong moves on to populate his actual, contingent, all-natural, empirically observable, physical world with beings that fit this description. Things which count as possible contingent natural beings, according to Armstrong, are actually instantiated Universals,[8] states of affairs or ordinary objects,[9] totalities,[10] and properties.[11] The world, composed only of natural beings, is according to Armstrong, the totality of Being.[12] Therefore, there can be nothing more than the world, or, in other words, if X is not part of the natural observable world, then X is not. For Armstrong, only those contingent beings which are actual, or instantiated, have being.

Aside from some obvious difficulties, Armstrong’s view of being is complicated by his claim that the future is, or exists.[13] According to his earlier claims, the future, if it (including all the states of affairs, properties, etc. that would be included in it) exists, is not a possible being, but an actual contingent being. Contingent in that it could possibly not exist, actual in that it does. What, exactly, does it mean to say that the future is actual? What is the ontological status of the past? If the future can be construed as actual, is it not reasonable to claim that the past is also actual? What, then, distinguishes the future, the past, and the present, in light of the fact that they are all actual, except our awareness of the actuality of one particular moment? Armstrong does not deal with these difficulties in this book.

An analysis of Armstrong’s doctrine of being leaves us with the conclusion that, for Armstrong, Being is a property. Being, according to Armstrong, is existence, but existence is only a property of the world totality, which is the totality of existents or beings.  Which is to say that all the constituents of the world totality are endowed with the property of Being. As such, the world totality state of affairs simply is co-extensive with Being. Anything that is not a part of the world totality state of affairs (those things which are limited by space and time) does not possess the property of Being. The world, as the ultimate totality includes other, smaller totalities, all of which must be within the world totality if they Be. As Armstrong says, “there are all sorts of totalities extending throughout being.”[14] It would seem, therefore, that Being is nothing more than a property of those things which are actual. Of course, for this to be true one must assume ahead of time, as Armstrong does, the truth of Naturalism, that all that has Being is limited to the space & time world. Does this not beg the question? If I define my terms such that only those things which are limited to the space & time possess the property being, then I should not be surprise to come to the conclusion that only those things which are limited to the space-time world possess the property of being. It has not been proved, it has been assumed. The system is coherent, in itself (only those beings that are physical and temporal are actual), and true, so long as there is no being that is actual and that is unlimited by space and time. Having shut up all the windows, and locked the door, the owner of the house can now sit inside and happily claim that there is no outside world.

We are still left at the end of this study asking the question, if being actual is all there is to being, then what does it mean to be actual? Can we analyse these terms any further? Why is it not possible for there to be some form of immaterial actual being, or an a-temporal actual being? After all, according to Armstrong the future, at least, is actual. But, then, what does it mean for the future to be actual? Another question that we want to ask concerns concepts and ideas. Do these have Being? What is the ontological status of their Being? Armstrong admits that his metaphysical system, based upon his basic presupposition of Naturalism, has difficulty with the philosophy of mind.[15] I would suggest that his system also has difficulty explaining what it is that distinguishes a human corpse from a live human. How it is that rational animals are able to distinguish between universals, properties, states of affairs, and the physical world that present these concepts (are concepts physical) to the rational animal? Finally, Armstrong’s theory will also have difficulty dealing with change. For example, how is it that a thing maintains its identity through change?



[1]D. M. Armstrong, Sketch for a Systematic Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), viii, ix.

[2]Ibid., 69.

[3]Ibid.

[4]Ibid., 1.

[5]This raises a further question: Does a concept have being?

[6]Ibid., 72.

[7]Ibid.

[8]Ibid., 17.

[9]Ibid. Cf. Ibid., 26. On page 17 he seems to equate states of affairs with ordinary objects.

[10]Ibid., 76, 78.

[11]Ibid., 16.

[12]Ibid., 98.

[13]Ibid., 104.

[14]Ibid., 76.

[15]Ibid., 105.

Popular posts from this blog

How Kant’s Synthesis of Empiricism and Rationalism resulted in Agnosticism

Immanuel Kant, presented with the extreme empiricism of Hume and the extreme rationalism of Liebniz, which he discovered through the writings Wolff, sought to take a middle road between these two extreme philosophical positions. I would submit that Kant’s synthesis of these two views leads to an agnosticism about what Kant called “the thing-in-itself”, and ultimately to the philosophical positions known as Atheism, determinism, and nihilism.


Kant’s Sources
First of all, Kant was influenced by Hume’s empiricism and Newton’s physics. He saw that the physical sciences, in contrast to rationalistic metaphysics, were actually making advances. They were making discoveries, and building a system of knowledge that accurately described the world of our sense perceptions. Rationalistic metaphysics, on the other hand, was floundering amidst the combating systems that the philosophers were erecting. It did not provide new knowledge, and only led to unacceptable conclusions, such as the Absolute Mon…

A Short outline of Charles Taylor's: The Malaise of Modernity

CHARLES TAYLOR’S THE MALAISE OF MODERNITY[1]
            This is simply an outline of Taylor’s basic argument in this short work written by Charles Taylor. The idea of this outline is to help the reader understand the book by providing a simple outline of the basic argument that Taylor is presenting here. The book, which is essentially the manuscript is the fruit of a series of presentations that Taylor made at the Massey Conferences which are hosted by Massey College and Radio-Canada, is divided into 10 chapters. In the first chapter Taylor essentially proposes three causes (recognizing that there may be more) of the Malaise of Modernity: (1) Individualism or the Loss of Sense, (2) The Primacy of Instrumental Reason or the Loss of Ends, and (3) The effect on society and politics in general of the loss of sense to an inauthentic individualism and the domination of instrumental reason, or, the loss of true freedom. Taylor considers the first Malaise in chapters 2 to 8, the second in c…

LEISURE: THE BASIS OF CULTURE – A BOOK REVIEW

Leisure: The Basis of Culture & the Philosophical Act. Josef Pieper. Translated by Alexander Dru. 1963. Reprint, Ignatius Press, 2009. 143 pp. $12.99. ISBN 978-1-58617-256-5.
            This book is composed of two articles written by the German philosopher Josef Pieper. Though the two articles are intimately connected, they form two distinct works; as such, this book review will begin by giving a brief introduction to the works in question, followed by and exposition of each of the works individually. The two articles that are included in this book, Leisure: the Basis of Culture and The Philosophical Act, were both published in 1947, and, as such, were written during the cultural crisis in Germany that followed the Second World War. Not only did Pieper have the cultural crisis in mind when he wrote these articles, but he was also writing in light of the works of the most well-known German philosopher of the time – Martin Heidegger. As such, any reader who is familiar with Heidegg…